VIII - THE ROMANCE OF ORTHODOXY
It is customary to complain of the bustle and
strenuousness of our epoch. But in truth the chief mark of our epoch is a
profound laziness and fatigue; and the fact is that the real laziness is the
cause of the apparent bustle. Take one quite external case; the streets are
noisy with taxicabs and motorcars; but this is not due to human activity but to
human repose. There would be less bustle if there were more activity, if people
were simply walking about. Our world would be more silent if it were more strenuous.
And this which is true of the apparent physical bustle is true also of the
apparent bustle of the intellect. Most of the machinery of modern language is
labour-saving machinery; and it saves mental labour very much more than it
ought. Scientific phrases are used like scientific wheels and piston-rods to
make swifter and smoother yet the path of the comfortable. Long words go
rattling by us like long railway trains. We know they are carrying thousands
who are too tired or too indolent to walk and think for themselves. It is a
good exercise to try for once in a way to express any opinion one holds in
words of one syllable. If you say "The social utility of the indeterminate
sentence is recognized by all criminologists as a part of our sociological
evolution towards a more humane and scientific view of punishment," you
can go on talking like that for hours with hardly a movement of the gray matter
inside your skull. But if you begin "I wish Jones to go to gaol and Brown
to say when Jones shall come out," you will discover, with a thrill of
horror, that you are obliged to think. The long words are not the hard words,
it is the short words that are hard. There is much more metaphysical subtlety
in the word "damn" than in the word "degeneration."
But these long comfortable words that save modern
people the toil of reasoning have one particular aspect in which they are
especially ruinous and confusing. This difficulty occurs when the same long
word is used in different connections to mean quite different things. Thus, to
take a well-known instance, the word "idealist" has one meaning as a
piece of philosophy and quite another as a piece of moral rhetoric. In the same
way the scientific materialists have had just reason to complain of people
mixing up "materialist" as a term of cosmology with
"materialist" as a moral taunt. So, to take a cheaper instance, the
man who hates "progressives" in London always calls himself a
"progressive" in South Africa.
A confusion quite as unmeaning as this has arisen
in connection with the word "liberal" as applied to religion and as
applied to politics and society. It is often suggested that all Liberals ought
to be freethinkers, because they ought to love everything that is free. You
might just as well say that all idealists ought to be High Churchmen, because
they ought to love everything that is high. You might as well say that Low
Churchmen ought to like Low Mass, or that Broad Churchmen ought to like broad
jokes. The thing is a mere accident of words. In actual modern Europe a
freethinker does not mean a man who thinks for himself. It means a man who,
having thought for himself, has come to one particular class of conclusions,
the material origin of phenomena, the impossibility of miracles, the
improbability of personal immortality and so on. And none of these ideas are
particularly liberal. Nay, indeed almost all these ideas are definitely
illiberal, as it is the purpose of this chapter to show.
In the few following pages I propose to point out
as rapidly as possible that on every single one of the matters most strongly
insisted on by liberalisers of theology their effect upon social practice would
be definitely illiberal. Almost every contemporary proposal to bring freedom
into the church is simply a proposal to bring tyranny into the world. For
freeing the church now does not even mean freeing it in all directions. It
means freeing that peculiar set of dogmas loosely called scientific, dogmas of
monism, of pantheism, or of Arianism, or of necessity. And every one of these
(and we will take them one by one) can be shown to be the natural ally of
oppression. In fact, it is a remarkable circumstance (indeed not so very
remarkable when one comes to think of it) that most things are the allies of
oppression. There is only one thing that can never go past a certain point in
its alliance with oppression—and that is orthodoxy. I may, it is true, twist
orthodoxy so as partly to justify a tyrant. But I can easily make up a German
philosophy to justify him entirely.
Now let us take in order the innovations that are
the notes of the new theology or the modernist church. We concluded the last
chapter with the discovery of one of them. The very doctrine which is called
the most old-fashioned was found to be the only safeguard of the new democracies
of the earth. The doctrine seemingly most unpopular was found to be the only
strength of the people. In short, we found that the only logical negation of
oligarchy was in the affirmation of original sin. So it is, I maintain, in all
the other cases.
I take the most obvious instance first, the case
of miracles. For some extraordinary reason, there is a fixed notion that it is
more liberal to disbelieve in miracles than to believe in them. Why, I cannot
imagine, nor can anybody tell me. For some inconceivable cause a
"broad" or "liberal" clergyman always means a man who
wishes at least to diminish the number of miracles; it never means a man who
wishes to increase that number. It always means a man who is free to disbelieve
that Christ came out of His grave; it never means a man who is free to believe
that his own aunt came out of her grave. It is common to find trouble in a
parish because the parish priest cannot admit that St. Peter walked on water;
yet how rarely do we find trouble in a parish because the clergyman says that
his father walked on the Serpentine? And this is not because (as the swift
secularist debater would immediately retort) miracles cannot be believed in our
experience. It is not because "miracles do not happen," as in the
dogma which Matthew Arnold recited with simple faith. More supernatural things
are ALLEGED to have happened in our time than would have been possible eighty
years ago. Men of science believe in such marvels much more than they did: the
most perplexing, and even horrible, prodigies of mind and spirit are always
being unveiled in modern psychology. Things that the old science at least would
frankly have rejected as miracles are hourly being asserted by the new science.
The only thing which is still old-fashioned enough to reject miracles is the
New Theology. But in truth this notion that it is "free" to deny
miracles has nothing to do with the evidence for or against them. It is a
lifeless verbal prejudice of which the original life and beginning was not in
the freedom of thought, but simply in the dogma of materialism. The man of the
nineteenth century did not disbelieve in the Resurrection because his liberal
Christianity allowed him to doubt it. He disbelieved in it because his very
strict materialism did not allow him to believe it. Tennyson, a very typical
nineteenth century man, uttered one of the instinctive truisms of his
contemporaries when he said that there was faith in their honest doubt. There
was indeed. Those words have a profound and even a horrible truth. In their
doubt of miracles there was a faith in a fixed and godless fate; a deep and
sincere faith in the incurable routine of the cosmos. The doubts of the
agnostic were only the dogmas of the monist.
Of the fact and evidence of the supernatural I
will speak afterwards. Here we are only concerned with this clear point; that
in so far as the liberal idea of freedom can be said to be on either side in
the discussion about miracles, it is obviously on the side of miracles. Reform
or (in the only tolerable sense) progress means simply the gradual control of
matter by mind. A miracle simply means the swift control of matter by mind. If
you wish to feed the people, you may think that feeding them miraculously in
the wilderness is impossible—but you cannot think it illiberal. If you really
want poor children to go to the seaside, you cannot think it illiberal that
they should go there on flying dragons; you can only think it unlikely. A
holiday, like Liberalism, only means the liberty of man. A miracle only means
the liberty of God. You may conscientiously deny either of them, but you cannot
call your denial a triumph of the liberal idea. The Catholic Church believed
that man and God both had a sort of spiritual freedom. Calvinism took away the
freedom from man, but left it to God. Scientific materialism binds the Creator
Himself; it chains up God as the Apocalypse chained the devil. It leaves
nothing free in the universe. And those who assist this process are called the
"liberal theologians."
This, as I say, is the lightest and most evident
case. The assumption that there is something in the doubt of miracles akin to
liberality or reform is literally the opposite of the truth. If a man cannot
believe in miracles there is an end of the matter; he is not particularly
liberal, but he is perfectly honourable and logical, which are much better
things. But if he can believe in miracles, he is certainly the more liberal for
doing so; because they mean first, the freedom of the soul, and secondly, its
control over the tyranny of circumstance. Sometimes this truth is ignored in a
singularly naive way, even by the ablest men. For instance, Mr. Bernard Shaw
speaks with hearty old-fashioned contempt for the idea of miracles, as if they
were a sort of breach of faith on the part of nature: he seems strangely
unconscious that miracles are only the final flowers of his own favourite tree,
the doctrine of the omnipotence of will. Just in the same way he calls the
desire for immortality a paltry selfishness, forgetting that he has just called
the desire for life a healthy and heroic selfishness. How can it be noble to
wish to make one's life infinite and yet mean to wish to make it immortal? No,
if it is desirable that man should triumph over the cruelty of nature or
custom, then miracles are certainly desirable; we will discuss afterwards
whether they are possible.
But I must pass on to the larger cases of this
curious error; the notion that the "liberalising" of religion in some
way helps the liberation of the world. The second example of it can be found in
the question of pantheism—or rather of a certain modern attitude which is often
called immanentism, and which often is Buddhism. But this is so much more
difficult a matter that I must approach it with rather more preparation.
The things said most confidently by advanced
persons to crowded audiences are generally those quite opposite to the fact; it
is actually our truisms that are untrue. Here is a case. There is a phrase of
facile liberality uttered again and again at ethical societies and parliaments
of religion: "the religions of the earth differ in rites and forms, but
they are the same in what they teach." It is false; it is the opposite of
the fact. The religions of the earth do not greatly differ in rites and forms;
they do greatly differ in what they teach. It is as if a man were to say,
"Do not be misled by the fact that the CHURCH TIMES and the FREETHINKER
look utterly different, that one is painted on vellum and the other carved on
marble, that one is triangular and the other hectagonal; read them and you will
see that they say the same thing." The truth is, of course, that they are
alike in everything except in the fact that they don't say the same thing. An
atheist stockbroker in Surbiton looks exactly like a Swedenborgian stockbroker
in Wimbledon. You may walk round and round them and subject them to the most
personal and offensive study without seeing anything Swedenborgian in the hat
or anything particularly godless in the umbrella. It is exactly in their souls
that they are divided. So the truth is that the difficulty of all the creeds of
the earth is not as alleged in this cheap maxim: that they agree in meaning,
but differ in machinery. It is exactly the opposite. They agree in machinery;
almost every great religion on earth works with the same external methods, with
priests, scriptures, altars, sworn brotherhoods, special feasts. They agree in
the mode of teaching; what they differ about is the thing to be taught. Pagan
optimists and Eastern pessimists would both have temples, just as Liberals and
Tories would both have newspapers. Creeds that exist to destroy each other both
have scriptures, just as armies that exist to destroy each other both have
guns.
The great example of this alleged identity of all
human religions is the alleged spiritual identity of Buddhism and Christianity.
Those who adopt this theory generally avoid the ethics of most other creeds,
except, indeed, Confucianism, which they like because it is not a creed. But
they are cautious in their praises of Mahommedanism, generally confining
themselves to imposing its morality only upon the refreshment of the lower
classes. They seldom suggest the Mahommedan view of marriage (for which there
is a great deal to be said), and towards Thugs and fetish worshippers their
attitude may even be called cold. But in the case of the great religion of
Gautama they feel sincerely a similarity.
Students of popular science, like Mr. Blatchford,
are always insisting that Christianity and Buddhism are very much alike, especially
Buddhism. This is generally believed, and I believed it myself until I read a
book giving the reasons for it. The reasons were of two kinds: resemblances
that meant nothing because they were common to all humanity, and resemblances
which were not resemblances at all. The author solemnly explained that the two
creeds were alike in things in which all creeds are alike, or else he described
them as alike in some point in which they are quite obviously different. Thus,
as a case of the first class, he said that both Christ and Buddha were called
by the divine voice coming out of the sky, as if you would expect the divine
voice to come out of the coal-cellar. Or, again, it was gravely urged that
these two Eastern teachers, by a singular coincidence, both had to do with the
washing of feet. You might as well say that it was a remarkable coincidence
that they both had feet to wash. And the other class of similarities were those
which simply were not similar. Thus this reconciler of the two religions draws earnest
attention to the fact that at certain religious feasts the robe of the Lama is
rent in pieces out of respect, and the remnants highly valued. But this is the
reverse of a resemblance, for the garments of Christ were not rent in pieces
out of respect, but out of derision; and the remnants were not highly valued
except for what they would fetch in the rag shops. It is rather like alluding
to the obvious connection between the two ceremonies of the sword: when it taps
a man's shoulder, and when it cuts off his head. It is not at all similar for
the man. These scraps of puerile pedantry would indeed matter little if it were
not also true that the alleged philosophical resemblances are also of these two
kinds, either proving too much or not proving anything. That Buddhism approves
of mercy or of self-restraint is not to say that it is specially like
Christianity; it is only to say that it is not utterly unlike all human
existence. Buddhists disapprove in theory of cruelty or excess because all sane
human beings disapprove in theory of cruelty or excess. But to say that
Buddhism and Christianity give the same philosophy of these things is simply
false. All humanity does agree that we are in a net of sin. Most of humanity
agrees that there is some way out. But as to what is the way out, I do not
think that there are two institutions in the universe which contradict each
other so flatly as Buddhism and Christianity.
Even when I thought, with most other
well-informed, though unscholarly, people, that Buddhism and Christianity were
alike, there was one thing about them that always perplexed me; I mean the
startling difference in their type of religious art. I do not mean in its
technical style of representation, but in the things that it was manifestly
meant to represent. No two ideals could be more opposite than a Christian saint
in a Gothic cathedral and a Buddhist saint in a Chinese temple. The opposition
exists at every point; but perhaps the shortest statement of it is that the
Buddhist saint always has his eyes shut, while the Christian saint always has
them very wide open. The Buddhist saint has a sleek and harmonious body, but
his eyes are heavy and sealed with sleep. The mediaeval saint's body is wasted
to its crazy bones, but his eyes are frightfully alive. There cannot be any
real community of spirit between forces that produced symbols so different as
that. Granted that both images are extravagances, are perversions of the pure
creed, it must be a real divergence which could produce such opposite
extravagances. The Buddhist is looking with a peculiar intentness inwards. The
Christian is staring with a frantic intentness outwards. If we follow that clue
steadily we shall find some interesting things.
A short time ago Mrs. Besant, in an interesting
essay, announced that there was only one religion in the world, that all faiths
were only versions or perversions of it, and that she was quite prepared to say
what it was. According to Mrs. Besant this universal Church is simply the
universal self. It is the doctrine that we are really all one person; that
there are no real walls of individuality between man and man. If I may put it
so, she does not tell us to love our neighbours; she tells us to be our
neighbours. That is Mrs. Besant's thoughtful and suggestive description of the
religion in which all men must find themselves in agreement. And I never heard
of any suggestion in my life with which I more violently disagree. I want to
love my neighbour not because he is I, but precisely because he is not I. I
want to adore the world, not as one likes a looking-glass, because it is one's
self, but as one loves a woman, because she is entirely different. If souls are
separate love is possible. If souls are united love is obviously impossible. A
man may be said loosely to love himself, but he can hardly fall in love with
himself, or, if he does, it must be a monotonous courtship. If the world is
full of real selves, they can be really unselfish selves. But upon Mrs.
Besant's principle the whole cosmos is only one enormously selfish person.
It is just here that Buddhism is on the side of
modern pantheism and immanence. And it is just here that Christianity is on the
side of humanity and liberty and love. Love desires personality; therefore love
desires division. It is the instinct of Christianity to be glad that God has
broken the universe into little pieces, because they are living pieces. It is
her instinct to say "little children love one another" rather than to
tell one large person to love himself. This is the intellectual abyss between
Buddhism and Christianity; that for the Buddhist or Theosophist personality is
the fall of man, for the Christian it is the purpose of God, the whole point of
his cosmic idea. The world-soul of the Theosophists asks man to love it only in
order that man may throw himself into it. But the divine centre of Christianity
actually threw man out of it in order that he might love it. The oriental deity
is like a giant who should have lost his leg or hand and be always seeking to
find it; but the Christian power is like some giant who in a strange generosity
should cut off his right hand, so that it might of its own accord shake hands
with him. We come back to the same tireless note touching the nature of
Christianity; all modern philosophies are chains which connect and fetter;
Christianity is a sword which separates and sets free. No other philosophy
makes God actually rejoice in the separation of the universe into living souls.
But according to orthodox Christianity this separation between God and man is
sacred, because this is eternal. That a man may love God it is necessary that
there should be not only a God to be loved, but a man to love him. All those
vague theosophical minds for whom the universe is an immense melting-pot are
exactly the minds which shrink instinctively from that earthquake saying of our
Gospels, which declare that the Son of God came not with peace but with a
sundering sword. The saying rings entirely true even considered as what it
obviously is; the statement that any man who preaches real love is bound to
beget hate. It is as true of democratic fraternity as a divine love; sham love
ends in compromise and common philosophy; but real love has always ended in
bloodshed. Yet there is another and yet more awful truth behind the obvious
meaning of this utterance of our Lord. According to Himself the Son was a sword
separating brother and brother that they should for an aeon hate each other.
But the Father also was a sword, which in the black beginning separated brother
and brother, so that they should love each other at last.
This is the meaning of that almost insane
happiness in the eyes of the mediaeval saint in the picture. This is the
meaning of the sealed eyes of the superb Buddhist image. The Christian saint is
happy because he has verily been cut off from the world; he is separate from
things and is staring at them in astonishment. But why should the Buddhist
saint be astonished at things?— since there is really only one thing, and that
being impersonal can hardly be astonished at itself. There have been many
pantheist poems suggesting wonder, but no really successful ones. The pantheist
cannot wonder, for he cannot praise God or praise anything as really distinct
from himself. Our immediate business here, however, is with the effect of this
Christian admiration (which strikes outwards, towards a deity distinct from the
worshipper) upon the general need for ethical activity and social reform. And
surely its effect is sufficiently obvious. There is no real possibility of
getting out of pantheism, any special impulse to moral action. For pantheism
implies in its nature that one thing is as good as another; whereas action
implies in its nature that one thing is greatly preferable to another.
Swinburne in the high summer of his scepticism tried in vain to wrestle with
this difficulty. In "Songs before Sunrise," written under the
inspiration of Garibaldi and the revolt of Italy he proclaimed the newer
religion and the purer God which should wither up all the priests of the world:
"What doest thou now Looking Godward to cry I
am I, thou art thou, I am low, thou art high, I am thou that thou seekest to
find him, find thou but thyself, thou art I."
Of which the immediate and evident deduction is
that tyrants are as much the sons of God as Garibaldis; and that King Bomba of
Naples having, with the utmost success, "found himself" is identical
with the ultimate good in all things. The truth is that the western energy that
dethrones tyrants has been directly due to the western theology that says
"I am I, thou art thou." The same spiritual separation which looked
up and saw a good king in the universe looked up and saw a bad king in Naples.
The worshippers of Bomba's god dethroned Bomba. The worshippers of Swinburne's
god have covered Asia for centuries and have never dethroned a tyrant. The
Indian saint may reasonably shut his eyes because he is looking at that which
is I and Thou and We and They and It. It is a rational occupation: but it is
not true in theory and not true in fact that it helps the Indian to keep an eye
on Lord Curzon. That external vigilance which has always been the mark of
Christianity (the command that we should WATCH and pray) has expressed itself
both in typical western orthodoxy and in typical western politics: but both
depend on the idea of a divinity transcendent, different from ourselves, a
deity that disappears. Certainly the most sagacious creeds may suggest that we
should pursue God into deeper and deeper rings of the labyrinth of our own ego.
But only we of Christendom have said that we should hunt God like an eagle upon
the mountains: and we have killed all monsters in the chase.
Here again, therefore, we find that in so far as
we value democracy and the self-renewing energies of the west, we are much more
likely to find them in the old theology than the new. If we want reform, we
must adhere to orthodoxy: especially in this matter (so much disputed in the
counsels of Mr. R.J.Campbell), the matter of insisting on the immanent or the
transcendent deity. By insisting specially on the immanence of God we get
introspection, self-isolation, quietism, social indifference—Tibet. By
insisting specially on the transcendence of God we get wonder, curiosity, moral
and political adventure, righteous indignation—Christendom. Insisting that God
is inside man, man is always inside himself. By insisting that God transcends
man, man has transcended himself.
If we take any other doctrine that has been called
old-fashioned we shall find the case the same. It is the same, for instance, in
the deep matter of the Trinity. Unitarians (a sect never to be mentioned
without a special respect for their distinguished intellectual dignity and high
intellectual honour) are often reformers by the accident that throws so many
small sects into such an attitude. But there is nothing in the least liberal or
akin to reform in the substitution of pure monotheism for the Trinity. The
complex God of the Athanasian Creed may be an enigma for the intellect; but He
is far less likely to gather the mystery and cruelty of a Sultan than the
lonely god of Omar or Mahomet. The god who is a mere awful unity is not only a
king but an Eastern king. The HEART of humanity, especially of European
humanity, is certainly much more satisfied by the strange hints and symbols
that gather round the Trinitarian idea, the image of a council at which mercy
pleads as well as justice, the conception of a sort of liberty and variety existing
even in the inmost chamber of the world. For Western religion has always felt
keenly the idea "it is not well for man to be alone." The social
instinct asserted itself everywhere as when the Eastern idea of hermits was
practically expelled by the Western idea of monks. So even asceticism became
brotherly; and the Trappists were sociable even when they were silent. If this
love of a living complexity be our test, it is certainly healthier to have the
Trinitarian religion than the Unitarian. For to us Trinitarians (if I may say
it with reverence)—to us God Himself is a society. It is indeed a fathomless
mystery of theology, and even if I were theologian enough to deal with it
directly, it would not be relevant to do so here. Suffice it to say here that
this triple enigma is as comforting as wine and open as an English fireside;
that this thing that bewilders the intellect utterly quiets the heart: but out
of the desert, from the dry places and the dreadful suns, come the cruel
children of the lonely God; the real Unitarians who with scimitar in hand have
laid waste the world. For it is not well for God to be alone.
Again, the same is true of that difficult matter
of the danger of the soul, which has unsettled so many just minds. To hope for
all souls is imperative; and it is quite tenable that their salvation is
inevitable. It is tenable, but it is not specially favourable to activity or
progress. Our fighting and creative society ought rather to insist on the
danger of everybody, on the fact that every man is hanging by a thread or
clinging to a precipice. To say that all will be well anyhow is a
comprehensible remark: but it cannot be called the blast of a trumpet. Europe
ought rather to emphasize possible perdition; and Europe always has emphasized
it. Here its highest religion is at one with all its cheapest romances. To the
Buddhist or the eastern fatalist existence is a science or a plan, which must
end up in a certain way. But to a Christian existence is a STORY, which may end
up in any way. In a thrilling novel (that purely Christian product) the hero is
not eaten by cannibals; but it is essential to the existence of the thrill that
he MIGHT be eaten by cannibals. The hero must (so to speak) be an eatable hero.
So Christian morals have always said to the man, not that he would lose his
soul, but that he must take care that he didn't. In Christian morals, in short,
it is wicked to call a man "damned": but it is strictly religious and
philosophic to call him damnable.
All Christianity concentrates on the man at the
cross-roads. The vast and shallow philosophies, the huge syntheses of humbug,
all talk about ages and evolution and ultimate developments. The true
philosophy is concerned with the instant. Will a man take this road or
that?—that is the only thing to think about, if you enjoy thinking. The aeons
are easy enough to think about, any one can think about them. The instant is
really awful: and it is because our religion has intensely felt the instant,
that it has in literature dealt much with battle and in theology dealt much
with hell. It is full of DANGER, like a boy's book: it is at an immortal
crisis. There is a great deal of real similarity between popular fiction and
the religion of the western people. If you say that popular fiction is vulgar
and tawdry, you only say what the dreary and well-informed say also about the
images in the Catholic churches. Life (according to the faith) is very like a
serial story in a magazine: life ends with the promise (or menace) "to be
continued in our next." Also, with a noble vulgarity, life imitates the
serial and leaves off at the exciting moment. For death is distinctly an
exciting moment.
But the point is that a story is exciting because
it has in it so strong an element of will, of what theology calls free-will.
You cannot finish a sum how you like. But you can finish a story how you like.
When somebody discovered the Differential Calculus there was only one
Differential Calculus he could discover. But when Shakespeare killed Romeo he
might have married him to Juliet's old nurse if he had felt inclined. And
Christendom has excelled in the narrative romance exactly because it has
insisted on the theological free-will. It is a large matter and too much to one
side of the road to be discussed adequately here; but this is the real
objection to that torrent of modern talk about treating crime as disease, about
making a prison merely a hygienic environment like a hospital, of healing sin
by slow scientific methods. The fallacy of the whole thing is that evil is a
matter of active choice whereas disease is not. If you say that you are going
to cure a profligate as you cure an asthmatic, my cheap and obvious answer is,
"Produce the people who want to be asthmatics as many people want to be
profligates." A man may lie still and be cured of a malady. But he must
not lie still if he wants to be cured of a sin; on the contrary, he must get up
and jump about violently. The whole point indeed is perfectly expressed in the
very word which we use for a man in hospital; "patient" is in the
passive mood; "sinner" is in the active. If a man is to be saved from
influenza, he may be a patient. But if he is to be saved from forging, he must
be not a patient but an IMPATIENT. He must be personally impatient with forgery.
All moral reform must start in the active not the passive will.
Here again we reach the same substantial
conclusion. In so far as we desire the definite reconstructions and the
dangerous revolutions which have distinguished European civilization, we shall
not discourage the thought of possible ruin; we shall rather encourage it. If
we want, like the Eastern saints, merely to contemplate how right things are,
of course we shall only say that they must go right. But if we particularly
want to MAKE them go right, we must insist that they may go wrong.
Lastly, this truth is yet again true in the case
of the common modern attempts to diminish or to explain away the divinity of
Christ. The thing may be true or not; that I shall deal with before I end. But
if the divinity is true it is certainly terribly revolutionary. That a good man
may have his back to the wall is no more than we knew already; but that God
could have his back to the wall is a boast for all insurgents for ever.
Christianity is the only religion on earth that has felt that omnipotence made
God incomplete. Christianity alone has felt that God, to be wholly God, must
have been a rebel as well as a king. Alone of all creeds, Christianity has
added courage to the virtues of the Creator. For the only courage worth calling
courage must necessarily mean that the soul passes a breaking point—and does
not break. In this indeed I approach a matter more dark and awful than it is
easy to discuss; and I apologise in advance if any of my phrases fall wrong or
seem irreverent touching a matter which the greatest saints and thinkers have
justly feared to approach. But in that terrific tale of the Passion there is a
distinct emotional suggestion that the author of all things (in some
unthinkable way) went not only through agony, but through doubt. It is written,
"Thou shalt not tempt the Lord thy God." No; but the Lord thy God may
tempt Himself; and it seems as if this was what happened in Gethsemane. In a
garden Satan tempted man: and in a garden God tempted God. He passed in some
superhuman manner through our human horror of pessimism. When the world shook
and the sun was wiped out of heaven, it was not at the crucifixion, but at the
cry from the cross: the cry which confessed that God was forsaken of God. And
now let the revolutionists choose a creed from all the creeds and a god from
all the gods of the world, carefully weighing all the gods of inevitable
recurrence and of unalterable power. They will not find another god who has
himself been in revolt. Nay, (the matter grows too difficult for human speech,)
but let the atheists themselves choose a god. They will find only one divinity
who ever uttered their isolation; only one religion in which God seemed for an
instant to be an atheist.
These can be called the essentials of the old
orthodoxy, of which the chief merit is that it is the natural fountain of
revolution and reform; and of which the chief defect is that it is obviously
only an abstract assertion. Its main advantage is that it is the most
adventurous and manly of all theologies. Its chief disadvantage is simply that
it is a theology. It can always be urged against it that it is in its nature
arbitrary and in the air. But it is not so high in the air but that great
archers spend their whole lives in shooting arrows at it—yes, and their last
arrows; there are men who will ruin themselves and ruin their civilization if
they may ruin also this old fantastic tale. This is the last and most
astounding fact about this faith; that its enemies will use any weapon against
it, the swords that cut their own fingers, and the firebrands that burn their
own homes. Men who begin to fight the Church for the sake of freedom and
humanity end by flinging away freedom and humanity if only they may fight the
Church. This is no exaggeration; I could fill a book with the instances of it.
Mr. Blatchford set out, as an ordinary Bible-smasher, to prove that Adam was
guiltless of sin against God; in manoeuvring so as to maintain this he
admitted, as a mere side issue, that all the tyrants, from Nero to King
Leopold, were guiltless of any sin against humanity. I know a man who has such
a passion for proving that he will have no personal existence after death that
he falls back on the position that he has no personal existence now. He invokes
Buddhism and says that all souls fade into each other; in order to prove that
he cannot go to heaven he proves that he cannot go to Hartlepool. I have known
people who protested against religious education with arguments against any
education, saying that the child's mind must grow freely or that the old must
not teach the young. I have known people who showed that there could be no
divine judgment by showing that there can be no human judgment, even for
practical purposes. They burned their own corn to set fire to the church; they
smashed their own tools to smash it; any stick was good enough to beat it with,
though it were the last stick of their own dismembered furniture. We do not
admire, we hardly excuse, the fanatic who wrecks this world for love of the other.
But what are we to say of the fanatic who wrecks this world out of hatred of
the other? He sacrifices the very existence of humanity to the non-existence of
God. He offers his victims not to the altar, but merely to assert the idleness
of the altar and the emptiness of the throne. He is ready to ruin even that
primary ethic by which all things live, for his strange and eternal vengeance
upon some one who never lived at all.
And yet the thing hangs in the heavens unhurt. Its
opponents only succeed in destroying all that they themselves justly hold dear.
They do not destroy orthodoxy; they only destroy political and common courage
sense. They do not prove that Adam was not responsible to God; how could they
prove it? They only prove (from their premises) that the Czar is not
responsible to Russia. They do not prove that Adam should not have been
punished by God; they only prove that the nearest sweater should not be
punished by men. With their oriental doubts about personality they do not make
certain that we shall have no personal life hereafter; they only make certain
that we shall not have a very jolly or complete one here. With their paralysing
hints of all conclusions coming out wrong they do not tear the book of the
Recording Angel; they only make it a little harder to keep the books of
Marshall & Snelgrove. Not only is the faith the mother of all worldly
energies, but its foes are the fathers of all worldly confusion. The secularists
have not wrecked divine things; but the secularists have wrecked secular
things, if that is any comfort to them. The Titans did not scale heaven; but
they laid waste the world.
No comments:
Post a Comment